Scientism & Faith

 

 

 

 

The Philosophy and Faith of Scientism

 

 

 

by

Rob Lewis

17*****

 

Submitted to Dr. Mihretu P. Guta

Philosophy and Theology of Science

BIOLA University-Apologetics/Science and Religion Program

 

Date

12-1-18

 

 

 

 

 

 

 


 

 

Abstract

Scientism is a unique framework of epistemological justification where only those beliefs that are rational and warranted are those that are produced by science. The commitment to scientism includes philosophical and theological assumptions. This paper will attempt to show that strong scientism is not only irrational, but that science in general is burdened with philosophical assumptions and faith-like commitments that are not unlike commitments found in theology.

 

 


I.         Scientism & Theology

Science has played a major role in society, and over the past two hundred years has proven to be an incredibly useful tool in the advancement of our civilization as a whole, most obviously through technology and medicine. This recognized success has led some to conclude that science is the only legitimate means of gaining knowledge, called strong scientism, and others have concluded that while science is not the only legitimate means of gaining knowledge, it is superior to other forms, such as philosophy and theology. This less dogmatic view is referred to as weak scientism. Without question there is a western cultural commitment to scientific knowledge that holds science and its scientists in high regard in a way that seems to point to the fact that science has gained a new kind of authority and final say not unlike the prophetic and sacred religious writings once enjoyed in times past.

While scientism may be rejected as a serious philosophical position, it can readily be observed in culture and held perhaps unconsciously as science continues to be held in highest esteem in the public square. On the other hand, theology has been, as of late, confined to the world of values rather than included in the world of fact and objective reality. Lawrence M. Principe makes an important observation along this line of thought. Dr. Principe has two earned doctorates, a Ph.D. in chemistry, and a Ph.D. in the history of science. As well, he is the Drew Professor of the Humanities at Johns Hopkins University in the Department of History of Science and Technology and the Department of Chemistry. He states the following in his essay Scientism and the Religion of Science:

“Yet another development has been on the rise of the celebrity scientist. Such figures have authored best-selling books not so much to explain scientific ideas and discoveries, but rather to make expansive, sometimes shockingly bold, statements about larger epistemological and ontological issues and to declaim about the role of science, scientific methodology, and the scientist in human society and civilization generally…leaving the confines of their narrow fields of expertise to preach a political, philosophical, and religious agenda that cannot be supported by either their expertise or the methods they claim that science follows.[1]

 

Dr. Principe is referring to the likes of Richard Dawkins who is perhaps the best known celebrity scientist today, who once also held the Charles Simonyi Chair for the Public Understanding of Science at the University of Oxford. He has authored best-selling books that are not meant to explain a scientific discovery, but like his book The God Delusion, are aimed at making philosophical statements about the nature of belief in God. The point is that culturally there is strong evidence that science has received the highest authority and honor, and other branches of knowledge have been deemed less valuable and less objective. This is consistent with the existentialist movement to detach scientific research from the subjective and personal character of theological inquiry.[2] It is understood that science is objective, rational and concrete, while theology is subjective, irrational and abstract. This distinction is at the heart of scientism.

Philosopher of science, Tom Sorell defines scientism as “the belief that science, especially natural science, is much the most valuable part of human learning—much the most valuable part because it is much the most authoritative, or serious, or beneficial.”[3] Sorell goes on to add, “Other beliefs related to this one may also be regarded as scientistic, e.g. the belief that science is the only valuable part of human learning, or the view that it is always good for subjects that do not belong to science to be placed on a scientific footing.”[4] Other subjects would include theology, which, as noted above, has been categorized as subjective, and dependent upon unobservable and or untestable propositions, and therefore is of a lower class of rational justification.

This aim of this paper is to show that strong scientism is not only irrational but that even weak scientism is burdened with philosophical assumptions and faith-like commitments that are not unlike commitments found in theology. If faith is seen as irrational it must be in light of some stated criteria. The task then will be to uncover these criteria and apply them to science as well. The hypothesis is that when the criteria is considered, science will also require faith-like commitments of the same sort that have been used against theology to show that religious faith is irrational (faith here meaning trust or commitment without absolute certainty, empirical justification, or full understanding).  The argument is that both science and theology have room for faith seeking understanding, both serving as rational justification for belief formation.

 II.         Science & Epistemology

 To begin, it is worth attempting to address the question of science’s purpose and ability to provide justification for rational belief. Can science provide an absolute explanation for the way the world actually works? For the scientific realist, science’s purpose or aim is to provide truth-based explanations of how the physical world actually works. Some realists argue that even though past theories have undergone significant changes, some being overthrown as a result of scientific revolutions, our most successful and best theories today are not at risk of being overthrown like the less successful theories of the past. As Fahrbach Ludwig notes,

They are supported by extremely good evidence, practically all of which has been gathered in the last few decades (typically long after the theories were originally accepted). By contrast, practically all refuted theories, both of earlier and more recent times, were only supported by moderately good evidence at best…our current best theories have experienced big boosts to their empirical success in the last few decades…and are therefore almost certainly safe from scientific revolutions.[5]

 

The idea is that we can have confidence in the fact that our most successful theories are those that are least likely to be overthrown by revolutions, and therefore are good examples of science actually pointing to reality. This understanding of science is at the heart of scientism, since the belief is that science actually describes reality better than any other branch of human knowledge. For the antirealist, science is simply providing useful theories that may or may not actually point to truth, while the modest scientific realist argues that science does aim at truth, yet not all theories warrant the same level of confidence. A certain openness is in order so as to allow for theories to be improved upon or even replaced without concluding that absolute truth is required before belief.

Quickly it becomes obvious that there are many different opinions in the philosophy of science regarding the role and limits of science in human knowledge and belief justification. For the sake of argument, this paper will assume the modest realist position and work from that understanding in order to demonstrate that while science is at least in some degree aiming at and capable of providing truth, it fails to provide absolute certainty without any faith-like commitments. It is important then to review the way science is thought to be a reliable source of knowledge and examine whether or not there is any evidence of faith in science-based epistemology.

III.         Criteria & Justification

The question that must be addressed right off is the question of criteria. What is it about science that makes it a reliable form of justification for beliefs? Most understand that in science, truth is found in evidence, mainly that which is observable. This kind of evidence is empirical evidence, which is open to experience through the senses. Therefore, most believe that science aims at producing empirical evidence, the kind that satisfies the criteria of the empiricists, who argue that scientific evidence is to be experienced. Kia Nielson notes, “…to be an empiricist-any kind of empiricist at all-is, at a minimum, to believe that all of our knowledge and understanding of matters of fact-of what is the case-is and must be, at least in the ultimate sort, based upon or derived from experience.”[6] According to the empiricist, reality is known ultimately through experience. This empirical framework is how most see scientific knowledge working to provide justification for holding any belief to be true. If one is justified epistemologically in most cases when they hold a belief based on empirical evidence, then why not make empirical evidence a requirement for justified true belief in all cases? It seems that this is the case, and this very criterion is what could be used to argue against the rationality of theology, revelation and religious faith.

At first take, the requirement of empirical evidence seems to be reasonable when the conversation is restricted to scientific knowledge. Scientism claims that scientific knowledge is of the highest value, and this knowledge is thought to be the kind that is acquired through observation and experimentation. However, the question being considered is whether or not all legitimate human knowledge can be reduced to the kind of knowledge that is supported by empirical evidence, which is what would be required in order to say that scientism is even possibly true. But even if we restrict the scope to scientific knowledge, is it reasonable to require that sufficient evidence be the kind that is empirically verifiable? It seems here we run into a problem. For we know that even in science some of the most widely held beliefs cannot be confirmed through direct observation, such as the strong and weak nuclear forces, gravity, and mathematical theorems, yet no one seriously doubts their existence. This point is drawn out by the philosopher J.P. Moreland, “For one thing, scientific theories often deal with unobservable entities and processes such as quarks and electromagnetic fields.”[7] These are the kinds of things that are well established in science, yet are not directly observable.

Are we to conclude that unless a belief is based on empirical evidence we are not justified in holding it as true? If it lacks empirical evidence, is it then not only unjustifiable, but unscientific? It seems that this requirement is even too great for science. In this line of thought Alex Rosenberg notes that, “Scientific explanations are supposed to be testable, they have ‘empirical content,’ their component laws describe the way things are in the world and have implications for our experience. But almost from the outset science has explained by appeal to a realm of unobservable, undetectable, theoretical entities, processes, things events, and properties.”[8] Given the fact that science appeals to and accepts as true many things beyond direct observation, the question then follows: is it rational then to reduce scientific knowledge to that which can be experienced empirically? There remains a strong sense that this is exactly what science is. As the evidentialist would argue in a similar way as the empiricist, seeing is believing. This idea goes back to a time before the enlightenment, yet is no less present today. An example of the evidentialist concept of science can be traced back to St. Thomas Aquinas. St. Aquinas is quoted by Alvin Plantinga who notes that according to Aquinas, scientia is inferred from what is seen to be true, “Any science is possessed by virtue of principles known immediately and therefore seen. Whatever, then, is an object of science is in some sense seen.”[9] So it is the case that it is not simply a matter of what one believes, but also how one comes to believe, and the criteria set. If only scientific knowledge is legitimate knowledge, and scientific knowledge is empirical knowledge, then what is one to do considering the non-empirical knowledge crucial and well established in science, like electromagnetic fields, and electrons? This is interesting considering the fact that, as already noted, much of science is not available to direct observation and experience. The point is made that believing the right things are not enough, you are only justified in believing if you have observation as the foundational justification. This is the “how”, not simply the “what” in belief forming. Building upon this brief survey of science and epistemology, it is fitting to turn now to scientism and its underlying philosophical assumptions.

IV.         Philosophical Assumptions of Scientism

The role of science is to provide true explanations for how the world actually works. The claim is that science is uniquely qualified in accomplishing this goal because it is concerned with how one comes to a belief. The basic rules or criteria are set, justified belief is that which is scientific, meaning it is empirically verifiable, and observable. The criteria have been established so far to include outlining the way in which one believes. This is the first philosophical assumption of scientism, and in science in general. As soon as the conversation turns to meaning and ought and belief formation or epistemology, the discipline of philosophy has been invoked and hard science is no longer leading the way.

The second example of philosophy being assumed in science is basic logic and natural order. The law of coherence, the law of non-contradiction and the law of identity are assumed foundations in scientific investigation along with an assumption that things are generally orderly in nature. Without the basic rules of logic, which are beyond the authority of science, science has no meaning at all. In this way the scientist assumes a philosophy concerning reality that is not open to scientific investigation, and it does so out of necessity. To be fair, some have rejected philosophy as being capable of studying reality, since it does not deal with physical reality, and those who would make such a claim are physicalists who believe that nothing exists outside of physical reality. However, it seems that even the physicalist is practicing philosophy in making distinctions between their physicalist world view and the world view that philosophy is a worthy investigation into non-physical reality. The concept and or idea of physicalism is not itself physical, and matter is not the subject at hand in the distinction between this worldview and any other. Once again it is clear that philosophy is at work. But to push the idea further in showing that there is an underlying philosophy to science, it is worth quoting scientist-theologian Alister McGrath, “Science is concerned with the uncovering and representation of the forms and patterns that occur in the natural world…But how do we know that nature possess regularity? How do we know that there are uniform structures and patterns throughout the totality of natural order? Is this a conclusion of scientific research-or is it an essential assumption underlying this research?”[10] McGrath is highlighting this very case that science assumes knowledge about nature that guides empirical inquiry. McGrath goes on to quote Norwood R. Hanson in saying, “To gain knowledge of these principles by experiment and observation is to presuppose in the search the very existence of that which we are in search. If the principles are true, we cannot learn of it empirically, for the essence of the principle is that there is presupposed in every empirical inquiry.”[11]  The orderliness of nature and the ability to logically discern it is a philosophical assumption science depends upon.

Another example of a philosophical assumption in science is found in causation theory. Science is often aimed at solving questions regarding causation. Take for instance an early scientific inquiry such as understanding how the heavens moved, which then led the Babylonian astronomers to pioneer mathematical astronomy to document and predict particular patterns. This investigation into causation is what drove later scientists such as Copernicus, Kepler and Galileo to give the scientific revolution the start it needed in the proposing and clarifying of the Heliocentric model, which overthrew the ancient geocentric model held since long before the birth of Christ. On a large scale, astronomy aims at understanding causation, namely in what causes the stars and planets to appear as they do, but an underlying chain of events awaits the investigator who wishes to truly uncover the necessary cause that is actually responsible for the effect observed. Often what is considered the cause is not actually the primary cause, or even the kind of cause that can be isolated from other sufficient causes. As in the example of astronomy, there is planetary motion which is affected by mass, velocity, and gravitational attraction, which means knowing how the planets move is a much less involved study than knowing why they move in such a manner.

This is referred to as an INUS condition outlined by the philosopher J. L. Mackie, where a cause is insufficient, but necessary in a bundle of factors that were unnecessary but sufficient.[12] There potentially could be a nearly infinite regress into the causal chain to explain a particular event or phenomena. But most scientific explanations are content with stopping the investigation and explanation much earlier, assuming sufficient and necessary causation. This is where the debate over under-determinism in causation would come into play philosophically, but sufficient determinism in causation is assumed in science. This is actually consistent with the idea that science is not concerned with proof, but is rather concerned with coherence. As Owen Gingerich has been quoted, “…science as we have come to use it relies very little on proof. Science is primarily looking for a self-consistent description of nature that hangs together in a convincing way…Science works by coherence, not by proof.”[13] As is the case in epistemology, science must rest on assumptions at some point in the face of the collapse of foundationalism and the inability to perfectly isolate properly basic beliefs and necessary and sufficient causes. Absolute proof is out of reach, and coherence must satisfy the scientific investigator in explaining causation.

Perhaps the most obvious and relevant philosophical assumption in science is in the stated hope of finding a unified scientific theory of everything. This hope is expressed by the philosopher Thomas Cook when he states, “In this sense it is urged that the characteristics of scientific development is the growth of larger and larger systems, covering more and more facts under single laws. This may perhaps be taken to imply that when and if science itself became perfect, all knowledge would be consequent of one great law, and that idea is successful as a pragmatic approach.”[14] There is a philosophical assumption in believing that perhaps one day all knowledge will be unified in one great law, and that assumption is that all knowledge can be reduced to a scientific law, but that very assumption cannot be proven through empirical observation.

This then leads one to consider the dogmatic claim of scientism, that only beliefs that are empirically tested and verified are true and rational. As Moreland has pointed out, this claim is not a claim of science, rather it is a philosophical claim, and as such is self-refuting.[15] It is self-refuting because it makes a truth claim that if true, renders itself false. To claim that other forms of knowledge and beliefs are irrational is a philosophical claim, not a scientific claim that can be empirically tested, observed or falsified. What one then is left with is the fact that scientism rests upon a nonscientific self-refuting truth claim. This means that scientism is philosophical rather than based upon scientific justification and logically proves to also be irrational. This is not to say that scientism is irrational because it is a philosophical claim as if only scientific claims are rational, but it is irrational because it is a philosophical claim that discredits philosophical claims.

V.         Similarities of Science & Theology

As Wolfhart Pannenberg notes, “Knowledge must always begin with the universal and abstract and only at the end reach the concrete which all the previous, abstract approaches were ultimately directed.”[16] In both science and theology general truths are established first, and then upon the foundational ideas and concepts more specific and complex ideas are added. Likewise, it has been argued, in varying degrees of success, that there is no fundamental difference between the mathematician, the physicists and the theologian in that they all rest on basic axioms which cannot be proven, yet support all subsequent reasoning.[17] There is a point in which some truths are accepted in good faith and reason without invoking an infinite regress of justification. Some truths are known in context, and that context is important. As the scientist theologian John Polkinghorne rightly points out, there is no universal epistemology, “There is not one single, simple way in which we can know everything; there is no universal epistemology. We know the everyday world in one way, in its Newtonian clarity; we know the quantum world in another way, in its Heisenbergian uncertainty. Our knowledge of entities must be allowed to conform to the way in which they actually can be known.”[18] In both science and theology there is a certain mystery that remains out of reach, which requires a certain amount of faith that while we don’t know exactly how everything works, there is an underlying order, even if the order is full of antinomies.

In science, namely in physics, there are many examples of where a universal and simple epistemology won’t work. For example, we know that light is both a particle and a wave, which is paradoxical, yet not contradictory. There are matrix mechanics, wave mechanics, and the measurement problem of quantum theory, which is itself a paradox in light of the general theory of relativity.[19] As well, there is the problem of material particles and spectral gaps being measured differently even when just one atom is added to material that contains 10^23 atoms, while at the same time there is no way of calculating when the spectral gap might occur relative to a change in material size.[20] It is overwhelmingly clear that in science, epistemic humility is in order, and this humility looks a lot like faith seeking understanding.

In theology the same can be said to be true: there is faith seeking understanding. Seeking to understand reality includes seeking to understand the unobservable, immaterial necessary first cause. This can be done in two ways, investigation and revelation. The Creator can be known through that which has been created, and the Creator can be known through revelation and experience. This is the sense in which belief in God is rational if it is formed and sustained by good inference, or immediate belief through experience or revelation, and as Nicholas Wolterstorff states, “I see no reason to suppose that holding the belief that God exists as one of one’s immediate beliefs always represents some failure on one’s part to govern one’s assent as well as one ought.”[21] This, however, does not mean that religious beliefs can never be revised and/or corrected. Not unlike the case of scientific revolutions, theological understanding can be improved upon and progress in truth seeking can be made. Wolterstorff observes that even developments in science can impact religious commitment, “Christians have been mistaken in what they thought constituted authentic Christian following; and sometimes they have become aware of their mistake through developments in science.”[22] This simply means that in theology, like in science, there is a greater truth to aim at, and each investigator can commit and hold to beliefs of varying degrees of accuracy and explanation. The Christian scholar is not unlike the scientist in that the subject corrects and guides the scholar into deeper and more comprehensive understanding. No theologian claims to fully understand God, while at the same time he understands that there is a systematic framework that guides his schema development, which can be improved upon thorough testing and weighing faith like commitments, and making corrections as irrational and incorrect beliefs are identified. So too the scientist holds to a reasonably reliable systematic framework with the expectation of gaining a fuller picture over time, which includes abandoning false ideas and failed theories.

In another line of thought, there are some things to which science cannot provide answers that theology can, such as the origin of the universe, the origin of the fundamental laws of nature, the fine tuning of the universe, the origin of consciousness, and the existence of moral, rational and aesthetic objective laws.[23] In this way it is clear that as in some ways within science there is a need for a modular epistemology, as Newtonian and quantum physics require different frames of understanding, so too in the case of science and theology there is a need for a different frame of understanding in certain contexts. Some knowledge cannot be gained through empirical means, some knowledge rests upon revelation, the testimony of reliable sources and degrees of certainty. Even when considering the weakness of inference to the best explanation, it seems that at times we are left with such inferences when it comes to things like the origin of stars or the nature of the earth’s core.[24]

VI.         Conclusion

Scientism claims that only knowledge gained through the empirical scientific method is reliable, rational and valuable. It has been shown that this claim is self-refuting, and as it turns out, there are many philosophical assumptions foundational to science, and even in science, there are many things held that cannot be empirically verified. The point is that theology and science have a lot in common in that they both employ commitments beyond absolute empirical justification. At the same time both seek understanding employing systems that guide investigation aimed at producing true beliefs. In both fields, there is no single epistemology, and in both systems evidence is sought, theories are weighed and beliefs and commitments are clarified, and reformed and refined. And in both fields a certain measure of humility is in order as both fields present paradoxical truths that drive both the scientist and theologian to epistemic humility that looks a lot like faith. As the physicist Paul Davies rightly notes, even if science were to explain the world, we still need to explain science, and if physics is the product of design, it must have a purpose, and modern physics strongly suggests that purpose includes us.[25]

Works Cited

Cook, Thomas. "Science: Natural and Social." Philosophy of Science (The University of Chicago Press) 6, no. 3 (1939): 318-327.

Cubitt, Toby S., David Perez-Garcia, and Michael Wolf. "The Unsolvable Problem ." Scientific American, 10 2018: 28-37.

Davies, Paul. Superforce: The Search for a Grand Unified Theory of Nature. New York: Simon & Schuster, Inc., 1985.

Fahrbach, Ludwig. "Scientific revolutions and the explosion of scientific evidence." Synthese 194, no. 12 (2017): 5039-5072.

Gingerich, Owen. "How Galileo Changed the Rules of Science." Sky and Telescope 85. 3 1993.

Ladyman, James. Understanding Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge, 2002.

Loux, Michael J. Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction . New York: Routledge, 2006.

McGrath, Alister. Intellectuals Don't Need God & Other Modern Myths. Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1993.

Moreland, J.P. Christianity and the Nature of Science . Grand Rapids: Baker Academic , 1989.

—. Scientism and Secularism . Wheaton: Crossway, 2018.

Nielsen, Kai. "Is Empiricism an Ideology?" Metaphilosophy 3, no. 4 (1972): 265-273.

Pannenberg, Wolfhart. "Laying Theological Claim to Scientific Understandings." In Begining With The End: God, Science, and Wolfhart Pannenberg, 51-64. Peru: Open Court Publishing, 1997.

—. Theology and the Philosophy of Science. Philadelphia : The Westminster Press, 1976.

Plantinga, Alvin. "Reason and Belief in God." In Faith and Rationality, 16-93. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983.

Polkinghorne, John. Faith, Science & Understanding. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000.

Pond, Jean. "Independence: Mutual Humility in the Relationship Between Science & Christian Theology ." In Science & Christianity: Four Views, 67-104. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2000.

Principe, Lawrence M. "Scientism and the Religion of Science." In Scientism: The New Orthodoxy, 41-61. New York: Bloomsbury Academic, 2016.

Rosenberg, Alex. Philosophy of Science: A Contemporary Introduction. 3. New York: Routledge, 2012.

Sorell, Tom. Scientism: Philosophy and the Infatuation With Science. London: Routledge, 1991.

Wolterstorff, Nicholas. "Can Belief in God Be Rational?" In Faith and Rationality, 135-186. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983.

—. Reason within the Bounds of Religion. Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1999.

 


[1] Principe, Lawrence M. "Scientism and the Religion of Science." In Scientism: The New

Orthodoxy, 41-61. New York: Bloomsbury Academic, 2016. 41-42.

[2] Pond, Jean. "Independence: Mutual Humility in the Relationship Between Science & Christian

         Theology." In Science & Christianity: Four Views, 67-104. Downers Grove: InterVarsity

         Press, 2000. 72.

[3] Sorell, Tom. Scientism: Philosophy and the Infatuation With Science. London: Routledge,

             1991. 1.

[4] Ibid. Sorell, Tom. Scientism. 1991. 1.

[5] Fahrbach, Ludwig. "Scientific revolutions and the explosion of scientific evidence." Synthese 194, no. 12 (2017): 5039-5072. 5069.

[6] Nielsen, Kai. "Is Empiricism an Ideology?" Metaphilosophy 3, no. 4 (1972): 265-273. 266.

[7] Moreland, J.P. Christianity and the Nature of Science. Grand Rapids: Baker Academic, 1989.

29.

[8] Rosenberg, Alex. Philosophy of Science: A Contemporary Introduction. 3. New York:

Routledge, 2012. 142.

[9] Plantinga, Alvin. "Reason and Belief in God." In Faith and Rationality, 16-93. Notre Dame:

University of Notre Dame Press, 1983. 40.

[10] McGrath, Alister. Intellectuals Don't Need God & Other Modern Myths. Grand Rapids:

Zondervan Publishing House, 1993. 163.

[11] Ibid. McGrath, Alister. 1993. 163.

[12] Loux, Michael J. Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction . New York: Routledge, 2006.

197.

[13] Gingerich, Owen. "How Galileo Changed the Rules of Science." Sky and Telescope 85. 3

1993. 36.

[14] Cook, Thomas. "Science: Natural and Social." Philosophy of Science (The University of Chicago Press) 6, no. 3 (1939): 318-327. 323.

[15] Ibid. Moreland, J.P. Christianity and the Nature of Science. 107.

[16] Pannenberg, Wolfhart. "Laying Theological Claim to Scientific Understandings." In

Beginning With The End: God, Science, and Wolfhart Pannenberg, 51-64. Peru:

Open Court Publishing, 1997. 62.

[17] Pannenberg, Wolfhart. Theology and the Philosophy of Science. Philadelphia : The

Westminster Press, 1976. 45.

[18] Polkinghorne, John. Faith, Science & Understanding. New Haven: Yale University Press,

2000. 7.

[19] Ibid. Polkinghorne, John. Faith, Science & Understanding. 2000. 8-9.

[20] Cubitt, Toby S., David Perez-Garcia, and Michael Wolf. "The Unsolvable Problem ."

Scientific American, 10 2018: 28-37. 37.

[21] Wolterstorff, Nicholas. "Can Belief in God Be Rational?" In Faith and Rationality, 135-186.

Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983. 176.

[22] Wolterstorff, Nicholas. Reason within the Bounds of Religion. Grand Rapids: Wm.

Eerdmans Publishing Co., 1999. 95.

[23] Moreland, J.P. Scientism and Secularism . Wheaton: Crossway, 2018. 135-155.

[24] Ladyman, James. Understanding Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge, 2002. 211.

[25] Davies, Paul. Superforce: The Search for a Grand Unified Theory of Nature. New York:

Simon & Schuster, Inc., 1985. 243.

DNA & Specified Complexity: An Introduction by Jeremy Blatchford

DNA & Specified Complexity:

Many of us have had to face off against someone touting the abilities of evolutionary theory to explain the existence of life and all the complexity around us. For many, it is overwhelming to stand up against such arguments. After all, aren’t the majority of scientists these days evolutionists? How could such a vast majority be defeated by the regular layperson? To many it is an uphill battle against overwhelming odds. Thankfully, like David against Goliath, science is a battle of quality over quantity. Science is decided by evidence, not by majority rule.

Debating against an evolutionist is not for everyone. When we are neither confident nor equipped for such a debate, we often end up looking foolish or overstepping the evidence we thought we knew. This debate on origins can be a convoluted place; however, it does not have to be. Science at its best is often much simpler than we realize.

As Dr. Douglas Axe suggests in his book Undeniable,[1] we can trust our instincts when it comes to the existence of design in nature. When we look at cars, planes, the pyramids, and even books and computers, we can easily conclude automatically that these were all designed by an intelligent agent. What about similar design in nature? Don’t look too far, because that design is in you and me and every living thing: DNA. The DNA molecule is literally the blueprint for life. An evolutionist will suggest that it is changes to this DNA molecule over long periods of time that lead to evolutionary changes, but where did such a molecule come from in the first place? As will be explained in further detail in the following essay, DNA and its sister molecules RNA and proteins are carriers of what we call “complex specified information.” This argument, simply put, concludes that all our observations of complex specified information has come from an intelligent designer. Since DNA is exactly the same type of information as computer code (though vastly more intricate), such a conclusion of design can be applied to it. As such, unguided processes like evolution by natural selection are incapable of explaining its origins. If you can master the argument of specified complexity, you have a powerful weapon in your arsenal for the next discussion on the origins of life.

 

[1] Axe, Douglas, Undeniable: How Biology Confirms Our Intuition That Life is Designed (New York: HarperOne, 2016).

 

Jeremy teaches high-school biology and physical science. He earned a B.S. in biology from Simpson University, and is currently working on a Master of Arts in Science & Religion at BIOLA University located in La Mirada California. 

Jeremy teaches high-school biology and physical science. He earned a B.S. in biology from Simpson University, and is currently working on a Master of Arts in Science & Religion at BIOLA University located in La Mirada California. 

 

The Full Essay Is Available Below

 

 

_____________________________________________________________________________

Naturalistic Evolution and the Origins of Complex Specified Information

 

Intelligent Design & the Origins of Specified Complexity

I. Introduction

For many, the debate over the origins of life has been settled. It is often assumed that Charles Darwin rendered unnecessary any arguments that the complexity of life needed to be explained by something outside of nature. Darwin and his disciples have been confidently shoveling dirt over the opposition for generations. However, new arguments for intelligent design have arisen: the discovery of complex specified information in biological life has become both intelligent design’s greatest strength and naturalistic evolution’s greatest weakness. 

II. Evidence from DNA

Within modern genetic research, we have had many breakthroughs in the decoding of the DNA molecule. Deoxyribonucleic acid, (DNA) has been identified as one of the most efficient information storage methods ever known. Not even digital code from the most advanced supercomputers measures up to DNA’s compact and proficient design. Software pioneer Bill Gates said, “DNA is like a computer program, but far, far more advanced than any software we’ve ever created.”[1] Upon this incredible molecule, lays a code hidden within a sequence of molecules called base pairs. The pattern of these base pairs could be compared to a digital code’s language of ones and zeros. This information rich molecule contains what Dr. Stephen C. Meyer has called complex specified information.[2] Meyer explained,

The crucial biomolecular constituents of living organisms possess… “specified information” or “specified complexity.” Biological information… constitutes a salient feature of living systems that any origin-of-life scenario must explain “the origin of.” Further… all naturalistic chemical evolutionary theories have encountered difficulty explaining the origin of such functionally “specified” biological information.”[3]

Clearly it’s reasonable to doubt the ability of naturalistic evolution’s explanatory power for DNA if it cannot explain the origins of life’s instruction manual.

III. Specified Complexity

What is complex specified information, and why does this provide such a headache for naturalistic evolution? To understand this, one must first understand the terms “specified” and “complexity”. For example, when we see a set of letters like “ESGIUHKDMNB,” we see a rare or highly unlikely event. If I were to randomly hit keys on my keyboard, it would be highly unlikely that I would hit the keys in that same sequence. This makes this a “complex” sequence. When we see something more like “FOX,” we can identify it as a sequence that conforms to a previously known pattern, making it specified. The second case is not complex because it could be randomly reproduced with the proper amount of time. Now let’s combine the two examples. A sentence, such as “WHAT DOES THE FOX SAY?” is a chain of letters and spaces that are both complex, due to the difficulty of random generation in the perfect order, and specified, because they are ordered in a specific way that conveys a previously understood pattern. Likewise, DNA shows incredible levels of specified complexity in its informational storage. Meyer concludes “…my characterization of DNA and RNA [ribonucleic acid] as molecules that store functional or specified information is not even remotely controversial within mainstream biology.”[4]

George Wald once claimed, in Scientific American, “Given so much time, the impossible becomes possible, the possible probable, and the probable virtually certain.”[5] Wald’s claims, however, are based on assumptions that more time can make highly unlikely events possible. It is a common misunderstanding of probabilities to assume that with enough time, things that are astronomically improbable will simply come to pass. Wald even suggests that some scientists are openly returning to spontaneous generation to explain life’s origins.[6] If this is true, scientists would be ignoring the simple, yet conclusive debunking of spontaneous generation from centuries earlier because they have very few other choices to explain the origin of specified complexity with.

Is it possible to produce the key building blocks of life through a purely natural and random process? Director of the Biologic Institute Dr. Douglas Axe explains, 

A prevalent idea at the time was that proteins were not particularly fussy about the sequence of amino acids [the building blocks of proteins] along their chains, and even less fussy about the identities of the amino acid that end up on the outside of their folded structure. According to many scientists then, all a protein needed in order to fold was an appropriate placement of water-loving and water-repelling amino acid appendages along the chain.[7]

Simply put, it was commonly assumed that proteins were fairly easy to make. That notion, however, didn’t last long. Through his research on proteins, Axe has discovered that the odds of producing functioning proteins by chance were beyond his wildest imagination.

… I was able to put a number on the actual rarity—a startling number. With only one good protein sequence for every 1074 bad ones, I had found functional proteins to be…rarer than Denton’s criterion! Unless this number was overturned somehow, a decisive blow had been dealt to the idea that proteins arose from accidental causes.[8]

To put that 1x1074 probability in perspective, it is estimated that the “…number of stars may very well be around 1.2×1023  – or just over 100 sextillion.”[9] Through a process of randomly mutating sequences of the amino acids in proteins, Axe discovered that chance alone could not explain the origins of these molecules. Therefore, the identification of specified complexity in DNA forces researchers to look for answers in places other than random recombination. 

IV. Interconnectivity in DNA, RNA, and Proteins

By definition, natural selection, the proposed mechanism that drives evolution forward, can only work on living, self-replicating organisms. Natural selection cannot apply to chemicals, and this is where evolutionary theory has problems: DNA requires proteins to read it, package it, maintain and fix it. Even DNA reproduction requires proteins. RNA, a copy of DNA, is required to produce proteins, both because it brings the instructions for the proteins and because it constitutes a functioning portion of the process that produces protein strands. RNA relies on DNA for its information and proteins for forming it as a copy of that information. This leads to one significant puzzle of interconnectivity and instigates a chicken and egg scenario: which came first: the DNA, the RNA, or the protein? Natural selection cannot produce all three parts simultaneously. Robert F. Service states:

In order for life to have gotten started, there must have been a genetic molecule—something like DNA or RNA—capable of passing along blueprints for making proteins, the workhorse molecules of life. But modern cells can’t copy DNA and RNA without the help of proteins themselves.[10]

Even though this seems to be quite puzzling, some evolutionary science writers suggest that it could still be solved. Service continues

Chemists report today that a pair of simple compounds, which would have been abundant on early Earth, can give rise to a network of simple reactions that produce the three major classes of biomolecules—nucleic acids, amino acids, and lipids—needed for the earliest form of life to get its start. Although the new work does not prove that this is how life started, it may eventually help explain one of the deepest mysteries in modern science.[11]

By claiming that the building blocks of life are fairly easy to get started, many imply that the rest of the process of building a living organism should fall into place rather easily.

The issue here is that these biomolecules are just the building blocks. As Axe’s research shows, putting those biomolecules together in a functional order is inconceivably difficult.[12] One could compare this situation to having all the parts to an automobile, but leaving random chance to put all of them together in a functional manner.

V. Other Explanations for Origins of Complex Specified Information

If complex specified information cannot be explained by natural selection, what else could account for it? There are only three possibilities left. One is the random recombination of parts that just happened to produce a functioning molecule that included specified information. Imagine, for a moment, that DNA was a book of blank pages. Now, picture a stream of random letters, numbers, and punctuation appearing on those pages until every page was filled. Would it be logical to think that the product is now a novel? Of course not! It would be gibberish. If occasional words did appear, they would soon be consumed by the degenerative nature of random mutations. If a few words appeared, they are still worthless since they have neither context nor function. Logically, if a string of letters such as “FORWUBFAWAS” appears at random, we may notice “FOR” and “WAS,” but in their context, they lack any value. In DNA, a single “word” means nothing in functional terms if there isn’t a sentence around it. An instruction manual is an apt comparison to DNA because one needs to see all the steps to be able to build the functioning product. Famous atheist Richard Dawkins has recognized these similarities: “The machine code of the genes is uncannily computer-like. Apart from differences in jargon, the pages of a molecular biology journal might be interchanged with those of a computer engineering journal.”[13] If a prominent supporter of the naturalistic evolutionary view sees this comparison, one should take note.

 However, Dawkins suggests that this design is illusory and “…the living results of natural selection overwhelmingly impress us with the appearance of design as if by a master watchmaker, [they] impress us with the illusion of design and planning.”[14] Dawkins would conclude that our notions of design are flawed and that natural selection, a directionless process could create the illusion of design; however, this ignores the observational nature of the scientific method.

However, is Dawkins correct that our intuitions about design are not trustworthy? Axe wrote, “…whenever we think we would be unable to achieve a particular useful result without first learning how, we judge that result to be unattainable by accident.”[15] Thus, our design intuition can be scientifically observed to be correct. We can look back at Bill Gates’ comparison of DNA to computer code: what is the only observable source for the information found in computer code? An intelligent mind is the only known cause, and science must be based upon our observations. Thus, using proper scientific methodology, we must conclude based on our observations, that, because DNA contains such a richness of functional information, it must come from a similar source as computer code, written novels, or instruction manuals: an intelligent mind.

If the origins of information cannot be traced from natural selection or random processes, then what other options are there? In 1969, Dean Kenyon, Professor Emeritus of Biology at San Francisco State University, and coauthor Gary Steinman developed an idea in a book entitled Biochemical Predestination. They argued that life might have been “biochemically predestined” by the properties of attraction existing between its constituent chemical parts, particularly among the amino acids in proteins.”[16] Their textbook became a predominant text on chemical evolutionary theory, and suggested that there were predispositions in molecular attractions in these biomolecules that made functional proteins not just likely, but necessary.

However, Kenyon himself eventually discredited his own theory. “Ironically… Dean Kenyon has now explicitly repudiated such theories as both incompatible with empirical findings and theoretically incoherent.”[17] Simply put, any attractions seen in the bonding of amino acids “…do not correlate to actual sequences in large classes of known proteins”[18] Some amino acids have particular attractions to others, but they are not strong enough to force the particular functional order needed to get the working proteins we see today.

Explaining DNA’s information-rich sequences by appealing to differential bonding affinities meant that there had to be chemical bonds of differing strength between the different bases along the information-bearing axis of the DNA molecule. Yet, as it turns out… there are no bonds at all between the critical information-bearing bases in DNA.[19]

Because there are no actual chemical bonds between the information storing base pairs in DNA, there is no way that stronger bonding attractions in biochemical predestination could explain the existence of DNA’s complex specified information.

If neither natural selection, random chance, nor chemical necessity can explain the origin of complex specified information, then what else is left? Logically, if an event cannot happen through these mechanisms, there is only one reasonable alternative. Intelligent design has the explanatory power to help us comprehend the origins of these complex biomolecules and their complex specified information, because “Intelligent design is the scientific study of the intelligible principle of biological function.”[20] Because the functions are complex and specified, an intelligent cause is the only logical answer to the origins of this information. In all our common observations, we see similar types of information only in books, digital code, and other analogous sources. Where does this breed of information come from? Do books write themselves? Can a computer randomly produce more functional code? No, these things require an intelligent source to infuse more information into them. The intelligent causation of life, therefore, is the only scientifically viable explanation we have left. Naturalistic evolution has been buried under the burden of proof, while Intelligent Design should take its earned place at the forefront of science.

 

 

Works cited

 

Axe, Douglas, Undeniable: How Biology Confirms Our Intuition That Life is Designed (New York: HarperOne, 2016), 33-34.

 

Dawkins, Richard. River Out of Eden: A Darwinian View of Life (New York: Basic Books/Harper Collins, 1995), 17.

 

Dawkins, Richard. The Blind Watchmaker (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1986), 21.

 

Egnor, Michael, “Life is a ‘Distinguished Outcome,’” Evolution news and Views, (Nov. 2015), http://www.evolutionnews.org/2015/11/life_is_a_disti101061.html (accessed Sept 19, 2016)

 

Gates, Bill, The Road Ahead (Boulder, Colo.: Blue Penguin, 1996), 228.

 

Kenyon, Dean and Steinman, Gary, Biochemical Predestination, 199–211, 263–66, quoted in Stephen C. Meyer, “DNA and the Origin of Life” in Darwinism, Design and Public Education (Rhetoric & Public Affairs), ed. John Campbell and Stephen C. Meyer (Michigan State University Press, 2003), 248.

 

Meyer, Stephen C., “Denying the Signature: Functional Information Is the Fact to Be Explained,” Evolution News and Views (Nov. 2015), http://www.evolutionnews.org/2015/11/denying_the_sig_2101021.html (accessed Sept. 15, 2016)

 

Meyer, Stephen C., “DNA and the Origin of Life,” in Darwinism, Design and Public Education (Rhetoric & Public Affairs), ed. John Campbell and Stephen C. Meyer (East Lansing: Michigan State University, 2003), 237.

 

Meyer, Stephen C., Signature in the Cell: DNA and the Evidence for Intelligent Design (New York: HarperOne, 2009), 109.

 

Service, Robert F., “Researchers May Have Solved Origin-of-life Conundrum,” Science (March 2015), http://www.sciencemag.org/news/2015/03/researchers-may-have-solved-origin-life-conundrum (accessed Sept. 15th, 2016)

 

Villanueva, John Carl, “How Many Atoms are there in the Universe?” Dec. 2015, http://www.universetoday.com/36302/atoms-in-the-universe/ (Accessed 9/18/16)

 

Wald, George, The Origin of Life (Scientific American 191, 1954): 44-53, quoted in Stephen C. Meyer, “DNA and the Origin of Life” in Darwinism, Design and Public Education (Rhetoric & Public Affairs), ed. John Campbell and Stephen C. Meyer (Michigan State University Press, 2003), 237.

 

[1] Bill Gates, The Road Ahead (Boulder, Colo.: Blue Penguin, 1996), 228.

[2] Stephen C. Meyer, Signature in the Cell: DNA and the Evidence for Intelligent Design (New York: HarperOne, 2009), 109

[3] Stephen C. Meyer, “DNA and the Origin of Life,” in Darwinism, Design and Public Education (Rhetoric & Public Affairs), ed. John Campbell and Stephen C. Meyer (East Lansing: Michigan State University, 2003), 237.

[4] Stephen C. Meyer “Denying the Signature: Functional Information Is the Fact to Be Explained,” Evolution News and Views (Nov. 2015), http://www.evolutionnews.org/2015/11/denying_the_sig_2101021.html (accessed Sept. 15, 2016)

[5] George Wald, The Origin of Life (Scientific American 191, 1954): 44-53, quoted in Stephen C. Meyer, “DNA and the Origin of Life” in Darwinism, Design and Public Education (Rhetoric & Public Affairs), ed. John Campbell and Stephen C. Meyer (Michigan State University Press, 2003), 237

[6] Wald, The Origins of Life 1954, 44

[7] Douglas Axe, Undeniable: How Biology Confirms Our Intuition That Life is Designed (New York: HarperOne, 2016), 33-34

[8] Ibid., 57.

[9] John Carl Villanueva, “How Many Atoms are there in the Universe?” Dec. 2015, http://www.universetoday.com/36302/atoms-in-the-universe/ (Accessed 9/18/16)

[10] Robert F. Service, “Researchers May Have Solved Origin-of-life Conundrum,” Science (March 2015), http://www.sciencemag.org/news/2015/03/researchers-may-have-solved-origin-life-conundrum (accessed Sept. 15th, 2016)

[11] Ibid

[12] Axe, Undeniable, 57.

[13] Dawkins, Richard. River Out of Eden: A Darwinian View of Life (New York: Basic Books/Harper Collins, 1995), 17.

[14] Dawkins, Richard. The Blind Watchmaker (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1986), 21

[15] Axe, Undeniable 2016, 20

[16] Dean Kenyon and Gary Steinman, Biochemical Predestination, 199–211, 263–66, quoted in Stephen C. Meyer, “DNA and the Origin of Life” in Darwinism, Design and Public Education (Rhetoric & Public Affairs), ed. John Campbell and Stephen C. Meyer (Michigan State University Press, 2003), 248

[17] Stephen C. Meyer, DNA and the Origins of Life n.d. 249

[18] ibid., 250.

[19] Meyer, Signature., 243.

[20] Michael Egnor, “Life is a ‘Distinguished Outcome,’” Evolution news and Views, (Nov. 2015), http://www.evolutionnews.org/2015/11/life_is_a_disti101061.html (accessed Sept 19, 2016)

McGrath vs Dawkins

It is so rare to find two individuals who represent two different world-views having a respectful and rational conversation. In the video below, Alister McGrath, who holds three Ph.D.s from Oxford University, one in molecular biophysics, one in theology, and one in intellectual history discuses the existence of God with the famous atheist Richard Dawkins. There is much to learn form this discussion. Enjoy!

Here is the link: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=3LGm0iWPC80

 

An Old Earth & Deadly Timing

The Universe Is How Old?

There is no shortage of debate concerning the age of earth within both Christian and Scientific communities. There are many books published by well qualified individuals on both sides of the debate, which only makes the discussion that much more complex. However, overwhelmingly the majority of scientists, Christian and otherwise hold that the universe is old, and while a bit younger, the earth is also pretty old compared to what seems to be the majority view within lay Christianity. This is not to suggest that there are no scientists who are also Christians, who also hold to a young earth, or that only lay church folk hold to a young earth view. That is not necessarily the case. It is true however, that if you ask the average church member, you will likely get a young earth view, while if you ask the average scientist, you will likely get the old earth view. 

The standard agreed upon in the scientific community is that the universe is around 13 billion years old, and the earth is around 4 billion years old. While generally speaking, most Christians will argue for an earth that is less than 10,000 years old. 

So What?

The debate for Christians usually lands on two fronts, the literal reading of Genesis and philosophically dealing with death before the fall in an old earth view. More often than not, in my experience, Christians also assume that evolution and an old earth view are the same thing. It is worth exploring these details and discussing the merits of both views. However, it is also worth making one important distinction and while we are at it, throwing out one possible solution to the death before the fall problem.

An Old Earth View Is Not Belief In Evolution: 

Evolution is a very interesting discussion in its own right. The evolutionary view that won over was that of Charles Darwin. While he did not come up with the idea of evolution as some assume, his version which was based on natural selection was the version that eventually won out and is the version most of us grow up learning in biology class. The premise is that all life has a common ancestor and that natural selection is the mechanism that promotes decent with modification where the most beneficial traits are preserved, that is the traits that provide a reproductive advantage. These traits are passed down, and a simple explanation is offered, the fittest survive. We may rightly point out that even in Darwin's view that first organism was endowed with the ability to reproduce in the first place needs an explanation, but this is a conversation for another day.

The point is that just because a person holds to the possibility that the earth is old, even millions if not billions of years old, it does not follow that they are then committed to theories of evolutionary biology. These two ideas are completely different categories and while evolutionary theory does require lots of time, this in no way means that if it were given enough time with an old earth view that therefore it would be true. I personally lean more old earth, but I have very strong objections to the theory of evolution as the best explanation for the complex life forms we find on earth. Besides, evolution has nothing to say about how life began, the theory picks up once life is already on the scene. In summary, an old earth view is not belief in evolution. 

Deadly Timing: Death Before The Fall?

If the curse from the fall was that man would surely die, then what do we do with death before the fall if the old earth view is proposed? First, as a Christian, I think there is something to say for the idea that all of creation will be redeemed, and part of that redemption is doing away with death as we know it. With that said, it seems entirely possible that there was death before the fall, not human death, but death no less. There is no denying that human death and the curse are related, but it seems possible that there was animal and plant death before the fall. The easy thing to accept is plant death. Animals and humans were eating plants before the fall, and this was certainly the case of death providing life. We can say yea, but plants are different, which is true, but if we can say plants are different, than can't we say animals are also different? First off, what did the shark eat originally? Do we have to come up with some extra biblical explanation for how the shark ate seaweed originally? And if so, does that mean that the shark and the lion evolved into carnivores after the fall? 

I think plants are certainly different from humans, and their death before the fall poses no problem for the biblical literalist who objects to death before the fall. Then what about animal death before the fall? Animals are certainly different from plants and obviously also different from humans. But is there a biblical problem with animal death before the fall? It seems that the curse does in one way impact all of creation, but specifically man is told that he would die if he ate of the tree. We know evil was already in the world before the fall. Satan showing up and tempting Eve clearly shows us that this is true. So we can't say all evil is a result from the fall. In the same vein I would argue that it is possible that animal death isn't entirely the result of the fall. If we are consistent we would have to say some death preceded the fall, if only plant death, but if we are consistent then we also say sharks were vegetarians originally. The fossil records show animal life living and dying long before man shows up. But maybe all the scientists are wrong and they got all the geological dating wrong. It is possible. But maybe we really can't count the rings of trees, mine data in the ice cores from Antartica, or measure the universe in light years... Maybe... It is a lot to give up, and to me it seems unnecessary to pit the book of nature against the book of particular revelation. I say hold on to special creation, hold onto Scripture, but let us be careful to let each book speak as it was created to do, for they both have the same author. More on this topic later...

Rob

28000115_10214041794986626_775034206_o.png

Science & Religion: Oil & Water?

I work in the aerospace industry, and the company I work for manufactures a wide range of products for commercial and military applications, from Boeing to SpaceX. We have the ability to actually develop new alloys, and super alloys for high profile customers, besides hosting world class manufacturing capabilities. My role is unique. Because of my technical background in machining and industrial engineering, and my graduate work and experience in learning design and technology, I serve as the bridge between production and HR. I am tasked with developing and providing compensation structures and training for technical roles across North America, while supporting International sites as well. I work with a lot of very smart, very technical people all from different walks of life. 

Last April I was walking out of an office at one of our sites in Southern California and I ran into both the controller and director of operations in the hall way. We got on the topic of school, one of them had a degree in metallurgy, and they asked me about my education, and I mentioned that I earned my first graduate degree from Purdue, and that I was actually working on a second at BIOLA. They asked me what I was studying at BIOLA since they knew it was a Christian school. I told them that I was working on a masters in Science & Religion. They both looked at me like I was crazy! One of them responded, "Those two go together like oil and water". It was late, and they were in a hurry to leave, and it was no time for me to lecture them on the history of science and religion, but I did comment in response that historically that hasn't been the case. 

Modern science is a tool, a systematic method of investigating the natural world. A definition of science is hard to produce, but the nuts and bolts of science is concerned with testing ideas through repeatable and observable experimentation in order to provide the best explanation of natural phenomena. We need science, we depend upon it for nearly every area of our modern life, from the food we eat, to the healthcare we receive, to the weapons we develop and deploy in national defense. With all of this said, is science incompatible with religion? It can be argued that science was pioneered by men of deep religious conviction, and many of them thought that their scientific work was actually intertwined with their service to God, and historically there generally has been no conflict between science and religion.

Of course there are instances of clear tension, namely in light of the Copernican Revolution where the Catholic Church struggled to accept the heliocentric view of the cosmos, over what they considered to be a Scripture based geocentric model. But I would argue that this was for one, a debate between Christians, for Copernicas, Kepler and Galileo, developers and champions of heliocentrism, were all Christians, and it was the Roman Catholic Church that they were answering to. And two, while there may have been a conflict between scientists and religious leaders, this does not in turn mean that therefore there is a conflict between science and religion as two forms of human knowledge and experience. Galileo the scientist, who was also a Christian, found himself in a conflict with the Roman Catholic leaders, but this in no way ought to lead one to therefore conclude that "science" and "religion" were in conflict. Dr. John Bloom in commenting on Copernicus, Galileo, and Kepler states, "Historians of science today concur that these early scientists' praise to God was not mere lip service to the cultural conventions of the times: these men were genuinely praising God for what they saw. Science, the study of nature, was truly acting as a handmaiden to draw people to worship God." (Bloom, The Natural Sciences: A Student's Guide, 2015, 40.) 

Are science and religion in conflict? If the history of science has anything to say about this, it would tell us that it certainly doesn't have to be the case. While a modern culture committed to naturalism might see religion as something that is in conflict with science, it is worth noting that naturalism itself goes beyond science and steps into the world of philosophy, and itself can take on a very real appearance of religious commitment. Commitment to a cultural norm, commitment to the cultural power centers, and commitment to the men and women doing science, rather than science itself. For science standing on its own follows the evidence wherever it leads, and has nothing to say beyond the evidence. If the supernatural is by definition outside of the normal natural ordering of things, then naturally science would have nothing to say about it, and only when the scientist takes on the role of philosopher would he comment beyond the silence of science. 

I do highly recommend Dr. Bloom's book that does a great job of exploring the natural sciences from the Christian intellectual tradition. 

Rob

539350.jpg